Moore's paradox in speech: A critical survey
Philosophy Compass, ISSN: 1747-9991, Vol: 10, Issue: 1, Page: 10-23
2015
- 17Citations
- 50Usage
- 5Captures
Metric Options: CountsSelecting the 1-year or 3-year option will change the metrics count to percentiles, illustrating how an article or review compares to other articles or reviews within the selected time period in the same journal. Selecting the 1-year option compares the metrics against other articles/reviews that were also published in the same calendar year. Selecting the 3-year option compares the metrics against other articles/reviews that were also published in the same calendar year plus the two years prior.
Example: if you select the 1-year option for an article published in 2019 and a metric category shows 90%, that means that the article or review is performing better than 90% of the other articles/reviews published in that journal in 2019. If you select the 3-year option for the same article published in 2019 and the metric category shows 90%, that means that the article or review is performing better than 90% of the other articles/reviews published in that journal in 2019, 2018 and 2017.
Citation Benchmarking is provided by Scopus and SciVal and is different from the metrics context provided by PlumX Metrics.
Example: if you select the 1-year option for an article published in 2019 and a metric category shows 90%, that means that the article or review is performing better than 90% of the other articles/reviews published in that journal in 2019. If you select the 3-year option for the same article published in 2019 and the metric category shows 90%, that means that the article or review is performing better than 90% of the other articles/reviews published in that journal in 2019, 2018 and 2017.
Citation Benchmarking is provided by Scopus and SciVal and is different from the metrics context provided by PlumX Metrics.
Metrics Details
- Citations17
- Citation Indexes17
- 17
- CrossRef12
- Usage50
- Abstract Views50
- Captures5
- Readers5
Review Description
It is raining but you don't believe that it is raining. Imagine accepting this claim. Then you are committed to saying 'It is raining but I don't believe that it is raining'. This would be an 'absurd' thing to claim or assert, yet what you say might be true. It might be raining, while at the same time, you are completely ignorant of the state of the weather. But how can it be absurd of you to assert something about yourself that might be true of you? This is Moore's paradox as it occurs in speech. What is the source of the absurdity? And why does it strike us that a contradiction is somehow at work when there is no contradiction in the content of what is asserted? In Section 2, I describe Moore's formulation of the paradox and evaluate his own solutions. In Section 3, I discuss Wittgenstein's influence in solving the paradox. In Section 4, I discuss Shoemaker's priority thesis that once the absurdity in belief has been explained, then this will translate into an explanation of the absurdity in assertion. In Section 5, I discuss work on omissive and commissive Moore-paradoxical assertions, i.e. those of the forms p & I don't believe that p and p & I believe that not-p. In Section 6, I discuss work on assertions of the form p & I don't know that p.
Bibliographic Details
http://www.scopus.com/inward/record.url?partnerID=HzOxMe3b&scp=84920937691&origin=inward; http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12187; https://compass.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/phc3.12187; https://ink.library.smu.edu.sg/soss_research/1569; https://ink.library.smu.edu.sg/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=2826&context=soss_research; https://dx.doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12187; https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/phc3.12187
Wiley
Provide Feedback
Have ideas for a new metric? Would you like to see something else here?Let us know